ARTICLE 4 - THE MORALITY OF HUMAN
ACTS
1749 Freedom
makes man a moral subject. When he acts deliberately, man is, so to speak, the
father of his acts. Human acts, that is, acts that are freely chosen in
consequence of a judgment of conscience, can be morally evaluated. They are
either good or evil.
I. THE SOURCES OF MORALITY
1750 The
morality of human acts depends on:
- the object chosen;
- the end in view or the intention;
- the circumstances of the action.
The object, the intention, and the circumstances make up the "sources," or
constitutive elements, of the morality of human acts.
1751 The object
chosen is a good toward which the will deliberately directs itself. It is the
matter of a human act. The object chosen morally specifies the act of the will,
insofar as reason recognizes and judges it to be or not to be in conformity with
the true good. Objective norms of morality express the rational order of good
and evil, attested to by conscience.
1752 In contrast
to the object, the intention resides in the acting subject. Because it lies at
the voluntary source of an action and determines it by its end, intention is an
element essential to the moral evaluation of an action. The end is the first
goal of the intention and indicates the purpose pursued in the action. The
intention is a movement of the will toward the end: it is concerned with the
goal of the activity. It aims at the good anticipated from the action
undertaken. Intention is not limited to directing individual actions, but can
guide several actions toward one and the same purpose; it can orient one's whole
life toward its ultimate end. For example, a service done with the end of
helping one's neighbor can at the same time be inspired by the love of God as
the ultimate end of all our actions. One and the same action can also be
inspired by several intentions, such as performing a service in order to obtain
a favor or to boast about it.
1753 A good
intention (for example, that of helping one's neighbor) does not make behavior
that is intrinsically disordered, such as lying and calumny, good or just. The
end does not justify the means. Thus the condemnation of an innocent person
cannot be justified as a legitimate means of saving the nation. On the other
hand, an added bad intention (such as vainglory) makes an act evil that, in and
of itself, can be good (such as almsgiving).[39]
1754 The
circumstances, including the consequences, are secondary elements of a moral
act. They contribute to increasing or diminishing the moral goodness or evil of
human acts (for example, the amount of a theft). They can also diminish or
increase the agent's responsibility (such as acting out of a fear of death).
Circumstances of themselves cannot change the moral quality of acts themselves;
they can make neither good nor right an action that is in itself evil.
II. GOOD ACTS AND EVIL ACTS
1755 A morally
good act requires the goodness of the object, of the end, and of the
circumstances together. An evil end corrupts the action, even if the object is
good in itself (such as praying and fasting "in order to be seen by men").
The object of the choice can by itself vitiate an act in its entirety. There are
some concrete acts - such as fornication - that it is always wrong to choose,
because choosing them entails a disorder of the will, that is, a moral evil.
1756 It is
therefore an error to judge the morality of human acts by considering only the
intention that inspires them or the circumstances (environment, social pressure,
duress or emergency, etc.) which supply their context. There are acts which, in
and of themselves, independently of circumstances and intentions, are always
gravely illicit by reason of