When
Death is Our Physician
WESLEY J. SMITH
The
most effective weapons in the pro-assisted-suicide arsenal are
fear-mongering, distortion, euphemism, half-truths, and lies,
all deployed to the drumbeat of “choice.” False arguments are
gladly spread by the contemporary media, which avoid depth and
context, preferring 30-second sound bites, tabloidism, and
soap-opera shallowness. The best defense against this propaganda
onslaught is to be constantly about the business of spreading
truth. After six years in the moral struggle against the medical
culture of death, I can state confidently that the more people
learn about assisted suicide, the less they support it. The key
to victory is education, education, education. Here then, are
the facts.
|
 |
Wesley J. Smith
|
It is hard to tell the truth about assisted suicide. Or rather, it's
hard to get people to listen. Folks generally are about as eager to
delve into the issue of assisted suicide as they are to work out the
details of their own funeral. It's a delicate and unnerving subject,
involving the ultimate issues of life: the reality of human mortality;
fears about illness, disability, and old age; and the loss of loved ones
to the dark, dank grave. Thus simply getting people to pay close
attention to assisted suicide — to grapple with its threat — is often a
challenging task.
This is even true of people who are religious or prolife, whose faith
informs them that death isn't the end but the beginning. In my work as
an anti-euthanasia activist, I have often appeared in front of prolife
and religious organizations to speak about assisted suicide. More often
than not, event organizers tell me that the audience is one-half to
two-thirds the size of their audiences for programs about abortion or
some other issue of concern to these communities. This has happened so
many times now that it is a clear pattern.
I don't take the empty chairs personally. I understand the emotional
dynamic at work. Life is difficult and worrisome enough without visiting
the painful realm of assisted suicide. It is difficult, even for deeply
religious people, to listen, to heed, and to care enough to become
involved. But avoidance of the assisted-suicide issue is a luxury that
those who believe in the infinite value of all human life can no longer
afford, because battles over assisted suicide are being waged — and more
battles planned — throughout the country. Tragically, one major battle
has already been lost: Oregon legalized assisted suicide in 1994 and the
law went into effect in September 1997. Today in the U.S. a small number
of physicians participate actively in their patients' suicide, and it is
absolutely legal.
On the bright side, since 1997, when Oregon's voters refused to
repeal the state's assisted-suicide law, a broad-based national
coalition of diverse groups has formed to oppose the death agenda.
Disability-rights activists, advocates for the poor, professional
associations in medicine and law, and hospice organizations — all of
which tend to be liberal and secular — have joined with Catholics and
other religious people and traditional prolife activists to oppose
medicalized killing. And this collaboration has borne fruit. Since 1994
five states (Maryland, Rhode Island, Louisiana, Iowa, and Michigan) have
passed laws explicitly making assisted suicide a crime, while Virginia
outlawed it as a civil wrong, subjecting anyone who assists in a suicide
to civil litigation. In November 1998, Michigan's voters rejected an
initiative to legalize suicide by an overwhelming 71 to 29 percent.
(That's the same state that put the murderer Jack Kevorkian in prison
where he belongs.) National public opinion polls that used to show
consistent popular support for assisted suicide in the 70 percent range
now generally show support in the mid-to-high 50th percentile. Still,
the death tide is powerful and must be contained and further reversed.
The most effective weapons in the pro-assisted-suicide arsenal are
fear-mongering, distortion, euphemism, half-truths, and lies, all
deployed to the drumbeat of “choice.” False arguments are gladly spread
by the contemporary media, which avoid depth and context, preferring
30-second sound bites, tabloidism, and soap-opera shallowness. The best
defense against this propaganda onslaught is to be constantly about the
business of spreading truth. After six years in the moral struggle
against the medical culture of death, I can state confidently that the
more people learn about assisted suicide, the less they support it. The
key to victory, then, is education, education, education.
Refusing medical treatment is not the same
as assisted suicide
Too many people support assisted suicide because they have watched in
horror as loved ones were hooked up to medical machines and kept alive
against their desires when they were in the last days of life. The
threat of such abuse is fading as the economics of medicine moves
inexorably toward managed care in which profits are made from cutting
costs rather than providing medical services. Still, for many
non-ideological supporters of assisted suicide, “being hooked up to
machines” is the prime concern.
Frequently, in my experience, supporters of assisted suicide turn
into opponents once they learn that they have the legal right to refuse
unwanted medical treatment — even if refusing care will probably lead to
their deaths. If a dying person doesn't want a ventilator or kidney
dialysis, he doesn't have to have it. If he wants to die at home instead
of in a hospital, he can. No one need commit suicide because of fears of
falling prey to high-tech medicine.
Declining unwanted medical treatment is the philosophical foundation
of the hospice movement — which helps dying people die without killing
them. In hospice care, machines are out, high-tech medicine is out,
surgery other than as an elective procedure to relieve symptoms is out,
impersonal medical institutions are out. Nurturing is in. Pain
management and symptom control are in, as are spiritual and social
services. The goal of a hospice is not to extend life but to help dying
people live out their days in comfort and dignity and to care for them
in a setting of unconditional love. Hospice care works so well that it
is quite common for the dying person to declare that the experience of
heading toward death is a “blessing.” There, then, is true death with
dignity — and nobody gives anybody a lethal dose of poison.
Pain control is not the same as assisted
suicide
Assisted-suicide advocates often try to create a false moral
equivalence between the medical control of pain and so-called mercy
killing. Their argument goes something like this: Since some people's
deaths are hastened by the powerful medications often required for
effective palliation, and since such pain control is considered moral
and ethical based on the “principle of double-effect,” then assisted
suicide should also be viewed as moral and ethical because the intention
of assisted suicide is similarly to alleviate suffering. There's only
one problem with this argument. It completely misapplies the principle
of double-effect.
Double-effect recognizes that there are occasions when a person may
intend to do a good thing while recognizing that a bad thing might occur
despite all of his good intentions. Even if the bad outcome then occurs,
so long as the original intention was good, then the action is deemed
morally acceptable.
In order for the double-effect principle to apply — meaning an act
that produces a bad result is still considered to be ethical — four
conditions must be met:
- The action taken (in this case, treating pain and relieving
suffering) is “good” or morally neutral.
- The bad effect (in this case, death) may be a risk but it is not
intended.
- The good effect cannot be brought about by means of the bad
effect.
- There is a proportionately grave reason to perform the act (in
this case, the alleviation of severe pain) and to risk therein the
bad effect.
If properly applied pain control accidentally hastens a patient's
death, the palliative act remains ethical because the bad effect — death
— was not intended. On the other hand, assisted suicide intentionally
causes death as the means of alleviating suffering. Thus, it fails to
measure up to the principle of double-effect and therefore remains an
immoral and unethical act.
Pain control, like all medical treatments, whether surgery,
chemotherapy, or having a simple medical test, can have unintended
lethal side effects. Assisted suicide, on the other hand, has but one
intention — the death of the patient — that should not be confused with
its purported motive — an end to suffering. Assisted suicide is thus a
profound violation of the “do no harm” values of Hippocratic medicine.
Assisted suicide would not be limited to
people who are treminally ill
Legalizing assisted suicide for people who are diagnosed with a
terminal illness is wrong. To authorize doctors to dispatch dying people
sends the insidious cultural message that the lives of sick and dying
people are of little use or value. Kathryn Tucker, an attorney for the
assisted-suicide advocacy group Compassion in Dying, once argued in
court that the state had little interest in protecting the lives of
terminally ill people from suicide because their lives are not “viable.”
On the other hand, most opponents of assisted suicide understand that if
we are to value all human life we must treat all people equally. Whether
the desire to self-destruct is caused by serious illness, a broken
heart, or mental illness, common decency and compassion call for suicide
prevention, not the abandonment to death-facilitation.
That being said, most assisted-suicide advocates do not want to limit
death-doctor services to people who are terminally ill. Advocates are
well aware that popular support for assisted suicide evaporates when the
legalization criteria involve chronically ill, elderly, depressed, or
disabled people. This presents an acute political problem for them: They
want a broad license for medicalized killing but they know they can't
promote it openly because they will lose substantial public support.
As a result, advocates resort to using vague and expandable language.
In December 1997, shortly after the Oregon law went into effect, the
organization called Compassion in Dying of Washington released a
fundraising letter. The group had been a key participant in legalizing
assisted suicide in Oregon, and was now ready to move its death agenda
to the next level, writing to supporters that they needed increased
funding because:
We have expanded our mission to include not only terminally ill
individuals, but also persons with incurable illnesses which will
eventually lead to a terminal diagnosis. The need for increased funding
is even more crucial (emphasis added).
“Incurable illnesses which will eventually lead to a terminal
diagnosis” covers a far broader array of maladies than terminal illness,
and may include asymptomatic HIV infection, multiple sclerosis,
diabetes, emphysema, early-stage cancer, asthma, and many other
diseases.
Similarly, on July 27,1998, the Hemlock Society, perhaps the nation's
largest assisted-suicide advocacy group, issued a press release calling
for the legalization of assisted suicide for people with “incurable
conditions.” The use of the word “incurable” was intentional. Most
people think “terminal” when they hear “incurable,” but the terms are
not synonyms. Arthritis is incurable but not terminal. Often paraplegia
is too. Herpes, too, cannot be cured.
The true agenda of the assisted-suicide movement came into focus in
October 1998, when the World Federation of Right to Die Societies — an
organization consisting of the world's foremost euthanasia advocacy
groups — issued its “Zurich Declaration” after its biannual convention.
The Declaration urged that people “suffering severe and enduring
distress [should be eligible] to receive medical help to die” (emphasis
added). Finally, the actual goal of the assisted-suicide movement is
revealed: death on demand for anyone with more than a transitory wish to
die.
Guidelines will not protect against abuse
The assisted-suicide movement promises that abuses will be prevented
by so-called protective guidelines. But this promise of protection is as
empty as the repeated assurances that assisted suicide will be
restricted to the terminally ill. One need only look to the experience
of the Netherlands to see what scant protection protective guidelines
actually provide.
Euthanasia is not, at this writing, technically legal in the
Netherlands. But if doctors follow the legal guidelines enacted in the
early 1990s by the Parliament, and if they report euthanasia and
assisted-suicide deaths to the coroner, they will not be prosecuted. The
guidelines require, among other things, repeated requests by the
patient, and unbearable suffering for which there are no reasonable
alternatives (a guideline that does not exist in Oregon or in most U.S.
legalization proposals). The Dutch guidelines also require doctors to
obtain a second medical opinion before killing their patients.
In practice, these guidelines are ignored routinely or have been
expanded to the point where they are ephemeral. A recent study published
in the Journal of Medical Ethics about euthanasia in the Netherlands
reveals that the Dutch policy is “beyond effective control” since 59
percent of doctors do not report euthanasia or assisted suicide to
authorities as required by law. Worse, the categories of people who are
killed have expanded steadily since euthanasia effectively entered Dutch
medical practice. Today in the Netherlands, not only are terminally ill
people who ask to be killed euthanized but so are chronically ill
people. For example, a pro-euthanasia Dutch documentary, shown in this
country on PBS, told the story of a young woman in remission from
anorexia. She was so worried about returning to using food for self
abuse that she asked her doctor to kill her. He did, without legal
consequences. Such well-documented cases of out-of-control euthanasia in
the Netherlands abound.
Dutch doctors even kill people who aren't sick but only depressed.
There was a prosecution that failed, and it is worth sketching. A
psychiatrist assisted in the suicide of a depressed woman after having
seen her for only four sessions over a five-week period. The woman had
purchased a gravesite for three, had moved into it the caskets of her
two dead children, and had an obsessive wish to be buried between them.
The psychiatrist obliged. He was prosecuted, but the Dutch Supreme Court
— despite the doctor's admission that he did not attempt to treat her
before helping to kill her — validated his act, ruling that suffering is
suffering and for purposes of euthanasia it does not matter if it is
physical or emotional.
People who can't or don't ask to die are also killed by Dutch
doctors. Babies born with disabilities are euthanized at the request of
parents based on quality-of-life projections. According to a study
published in the July 26, 1997, edition of the British medical journal
The Lancet, eight percent of all infants who die in the Netherlands are
injected with drugs by their doctors “with the explicit aim of hastening
death,” which amounts to approximately 80 infants killed per year.
(According to the study, 45 percent of neonatologists who participated
in the study had killed infants, as had 31 percent of pediatricians.)
Many Dutch doctors also practice involuntary euthanasia on adults.
According to several studies conducted during the past decade, more than
1,000 persons who do not ask to be euthanized are killed each year by
Dutch doctors because the doctor's values dictate that their deaths
should be brought about — and this number does not include the thousands
who are killed each year by intentional overdoses of morphine.
Now, not satisfied with the radical medical killing license already
accorded to doctors, the Dutch government recently indicated that it
intends to legalize euthanasia formally. If they do remove the few
restraints provided by so-called protective guidelines, the consequences
will be gruesome.
Assisted suicide is not working well in
Oregon
Assisted suicide in Oregon operates in a shroud of state-imposed
secrecy. What little we know comes from the press releases of assisted
suicide advocacy groups and from a study published in the New England
Journal of Medicine which purported to shed light on the law's actual
workings. Assisted-suicide advocates claimed that the NEJM report
validated their cause. But a close reading reveals that the worries of
assisted-suicide opponents are entirely justified.
Fifteen people reportedly committed assisted suicide legally in
Oregon in 1998. (The study acknowledges that there is no way to know if
this number includes all of the actual assisted suicides. While the law
requires doctors to report all assisted suicides, it does not punish
doctors who fail to comply.) According to the report, none of the dead
patients committed assisted suicide because of intractable pain or
suffering that could not be otherwise alleviated. Rather, those who
committed the act did so based primarily on fears of future dependency.
This represents a dramatic expansion of the types of medical conditions
that assisted-suicide advocates had told Oregon's citizens the law would
end. These disturbing results demonstrate that assisted suicide, rather
than being a rare event resorted to only in cases of extreme medical
urgency, will expand steadily, just as it has done in the Netherlands.
Disability-rights advocates point out that allowing assisted suicide
based upon fear of needing help going to the toilet or bathing or doing
other daily-life activities will involve far more disabled people than
those who are actually dying. They also note that, like other
difficulties in life, dependency is a circumstance to which people
adjust with time. To accept that worries about the potential need for
living assistance are a reason for doctors to write lethal prescriptions
is to put disabled people at material risk and to send the message that
such lives are not worth living. That is why nine national
disability-rights organizations have come out strongly against
legalizing assisted suicide, and not one such national group supports
it.
The NEJM study also reports that the people who committed assisted
suicide had “shorter” relationships with the doctors who prescribed
lethally than did a group of control patients who died naturally under
their physicians' care. The exact time difference is not given but we do
know from earlier media reports that a patient's relationship with a
death-doctor is likely to be quite short. The first woman to commit
assisted suicide in Oregon had a two-and-a-half-week relationship with
the doctor who wrote her lethal prescription. Her own doctor had refused
to assist her suicide, as had a second doctor — who diagnosed her with
depression. So she went to an advocacy group and was referred to a
death-doctor willing to do the deed. Hers was not a unique case, as the
report shows. This isn't careful medical practice, it is rampant
Kevorkianism.
Assisted suicide would really be about money
In the end, assisted suicide would be less about “choice” than about
profits in the health-care system and cutting the costs of health care
to government. This is the conclusion of none other than Derek Humphry
and pro-euthanasia attorney Mary Clement, who in their new book Freedom
to Die admit that cost-containment may become the bottom-line
justification for physician-assisted suicide (PAS):
A rational argument can be made for allowing PAS in order to offset
the amount society and family spend on the ill.... Since the largest
medical expenses are incurred in the final days and weeks of life, the
hastened demise of people with only a short time left would free
resources for others. Hundreds of billions of dollars could benefit
those patients who not only can be cured but who want to live.
Imagine a health-care system in which the profit incentives favor
killing as the best “treatment” for cancer, Lou Gehrig's disease,
multiple sclerosis, spinal injury, Alzheimer's disease, and the many
other medical conditions that in some way touch us all. Imagine the
money to be made by for-profit HMOs if they are spared the expense of
caring for such patients until the end of their natural lives. (The
drugs for an assisted suicide cost only about $40, whereas it might cost
tens of thousands of dollars to treat the patient properly.) And imagine
the potential for abuse and coercion in a healthcare system in which
killing can lead to greater profits, not to mention increased stock
values and performance bonuses. Since our moral values often follow our
pocketbooks, the result would be a profound devolution of our culture
and of the ethics of medical practice.
To legalize physician-assisted suicide would be to take up again the
practices of ancient societies that exposed disabled infants on the
hillside and left the elderly and infirm by the side of the road.
Protecting the lives of vulnerable people against medicalized killing is
essential not only to this country but also to the world. After all, if
we can export rock music and consumerism, we can certainly export the
twisted values of Jack Kevorkian. That would be a tragic fate for a
country that Abraham Lincoln once called the last best hope of earth
ACKNOWLEDGEMENT
Smith, Wesley J. “When Death is Our Physician.” New Oxford Review
(December 1999): 26-31.
Reprinted with permission of the New Oxford Review (1069 Kains
Ave., Berkeley, CA 94706).
To subscribe to the New Oxford Review, call (510) 526-3492.
THE AUTHOR
Wesley J. Smith is a senior fellow at the
Discovery Institute
and an attorney and consultant for the
International Task Force on Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide. He is
an international lecturer and public speaker, appearing frequently at
political, university, medical, legal, bioethics, and community
gatherings across the United States, Canada, Great Britain, and
Australia. Wesley J. Smith is the author or co/author of 9 books.
Most recently his revised and updated
Forced Exit: The Slippery Slope From Assisted Suicide to Legalized
Murder,
Culture of Death: The Assault of Medical Ethics in America, and
Power Over Pain.
Copyright © 1999 New Oxford
Review
|